Post

What Distinguishes Life from Non-Life?

“How, therefore, we must ask, is it possible for us to distinguish the living from the lifeless if we can describe both conceptually by the motion of inorganic corpuscles?”—Karl Pearson (The Grammar of Science, 1892).

What Distinguishes Life from Non-Life?

Introduction

In 1892, Karl Pearson posed a profound scientific question that continues to resonate through modern biology and philosophy of science: What physically distinguishes the living from the lifeless? Despite over a century of biological discovery, including the molecular revolution of the mid-20th century, this question remains largely unresolved. Although the structure of DNA, the genetic code, and the machinery of molecular biology are now well understood, the reduction of life to chemistry and physics has failed to yield a complete account of what makes life distinct. Howard Pattee, in his seminal paper “The Physics of Symbols: Bridging the Epistemic Cut,” revisits this question by examining the epistemic foundations of biology. His argument pivots on the recognition that life is characterized not merely by the operation of physical laws but by the use of symbolic control structures that bridge the gap between abstract representation and physical dynamics. This essay explores Pattee’s historical, philosophical, and theoretical account, tracing how the notion of the epistemic cut provides the key to distinguishing life from non-life.

From Reductionism to Symbolic Control

At the turn of the 20th century, dualism and vitalism were increasingly dismissed in favor of a mechanistic worldview. Yet the emergence of quantum mechanics rekindled uncertainties about whether the physical sciences could fully capture the essence of life. Physicists like Niels Bohr and Max Delbrück speculated that life might require new principles not found in standard physics. This intrigue catalyzed the birth of molecular biology in the 1950s, which quickly amassed a remarkable catalogue of discoveries: the double helix of DNA, the decoding of the genetic code, the discovery of mRNA, and the mechanisms of gene regulation.

By 1970, molecular biology had consolidated into a robust reductionist framework. As John Kendrew put it, “conventional, normal laws of physics and chemistry have been sufficient”. However, Pattee contends that this apparent triumph of reductionism merely sidesteps Pearson’s original question. To assert that life is made of the same matter as non-life, and therefore follows the same physical laws, is tautological. What is needed is not a denial of physics, but a richer understanding of how biological systems use physical laws through constraints and symbols.

Pattee’s central concept is the epistemic cut, the necessary distinction between the observer and the observed, the controller and the controlled, or more fundamentally, between symbolic representations and physical dynamics. In living systems, this cut is instantiated in the genotype-phenotype relation, where rate-independent genetic symbols (DNA) control the rate-dependent construction of proteins. This dualism is not ontological but epistemic: it reflects the need to treat symbolic memory and dynamic laws as irreducibly complementary.

Drawing from von Neumann’s insights on measurement, Pattee emphasizes that no physical system can describe its own initial conditions. This necessitates a separation between the system being described (object) and the describing apparatus (subject). Similarly, symbols cannot be reduced to dynamics alone because symbols must be interpreted by a code or mechanism external to the symbol itself. The encoding of instructions in DNA, the decoding machinery of the cell, and the interpretive function of enzymes exemplify this.

Non-holonomic Constraints, Semantic Closure, and the Origins of Life

To explain how symbols exert causal influence over physical dynamics, Pattee introduces the concept of non-integrable constraints. Unlike rigid, holonomic constraints that reduce degrees of freedom, non-integrable constraints preserve alternative configurations, allowing for the storage and reading of symbolic memory. These constraints are evident in the allosteric structures of proteins, enzyme kinetics, and the functional dynamics of gene expression.

Crucially, these constraints are not derivable from fundamental laws. They represent historical, evolved structures that harness physical laws without being specified by them. This control is what enables replication, regulation, and adaptation—core features of life. By contrast, purely dynamical systems, no matter how complex, cannot instantiate this symbolic control without external coding mechanisms.

One of Pattee’s most profound contributions is the notion of semantic closure, the self-referential condition where a system’s symbols control the construction of its own interpretive mechanisms. In modern cells, genes encode the proteins that interpret the genetic code. This circularity is what gives rise to autonomy and individuality in living systems. The origin of life, then, is not merely the emergence of complex molecules, but the emergence of systems capable of semantic closure—of bridging the epistemic cut in a self-sustaining manner. This insight addresses a central paradox in origin-of-life research: the apparent chicken-and-egg problem between genetic information and its interpretive machinery. Pattee resolves this by emphasizing the co-evolution of symbolic memory and dynamic constraint mechanisms.

Pattee then partially solved Pearson’s original question, arguing that life cannot be distinguished from non-life solely by abstract definitions or simulation models: “It is not possible to distinguish the living from the lifeless by the most detailed “motion of inorganic corpuscles” alone. The logic of this answer is that life entails an epistemic cut that is not distinguishable by microscopic (corpuscular) laws.” What matters is the physical realization of symbolic control. Evolvability requires not just any memory, but a memory embedded in structures that reliably fold, bind, and catalyze. These molecules must navigate a delicate balance between stability and flexibility. DNA and proteins accomplish this with astonishing efficiency due to their unique heteropolymeric properties, degeneracy, and hierarchical organization.

At the end of his paper, Pattee goes further and identifies three key conditions for evolvability: (1) the accessibility of functional sequences in genetic space, (2) the reliability of their expression, and (3) the smoothness of the genotype-phenotype map. These are not abstract computational requirements but physical properties of real molecules. Hence, artificial life models, based on pure symbolic behavior, ignoring the physical constraints of molecular biology fail to address Pearson’s question. Since they all depend on internal fixed rules, the generated structures will have limited potential complexity, and in so far as any novel organizing arises from the outside environment, the novel structures have no possibility of reliable replication without a symbolic memory that could reconstruct the novel organization.

Conclusion

The distinction between life and non-life cannot be located solely in the inventory of physical components or in the complexity of dynamics. It resides in the organization of matter into symbol systems capable of measurement, control, and self-replication. This organization requires an epistemic cut and its physical instantiation through non-integrable constraints. Life, in Pattee’s view, is not a violation of physical law but an exploitation of it through symbolic control.

Pearson’s question remains vital because it asks not merely what life is made of, but what life does that non-life does not. Pattee’s answer is that life bridges the gap between syntax and semantics, between symbol and matter, in a way that no non-living system does. In this light, to study life is not merely to analyze molecules, but to understand the emergence of epistemic agents—systems capable of distinguishing, deciding, and directing their own construction. That, above all, is what distinguishes the living from the lifeless.

Multiple questions remain unanswered. While it is true that the semantic closure gives us a watershed to talk about open-ended evolution, Pattee himself has stated that open-endedness is a consequence of evolution. Therefore, a model capable of explaining the origin and early evolution of such a semantic closure is still pending. The concept of closure in general is quite ubiquitous in theoretical biology, from Maturana-Varela’s autopoiesis to Rosen’s closure to efficient causation, the latter being equivalent to the semantic closure proposed by Pattee. Thus, a theoretical framework is needed to unify all these conceptualizations, which seem to be faces of the same die, talking about the same thing from different points of view.

Desktop View

This post is licensed under CC BY 4.0 by the author.